Aristotle's Rhetoric
Previous Chapter

Book III - Chapter 18

Next Chapter

Next as to Interrogation. The best moment to a employ this is [1419a] when your opponent has so answered one question that the putting of just one more lands him in absurdity. Thus Pericles questioned Lampon about the way of celebrating the rites of the Saviour Goddess. Lampon declared that no uninitiated person could be told of them. Pericles then asked, "Do you know them yourself?" "Yes," answered Lampon. "Why," said Pericles, "how can that be, when you are uninitiated?"

Another good moment is when one premiss of an argument is obviously true, and you can see that your opponent must say "yes" if you ask him whether the other is true. Having first got this answer about the other, do not go on to ask him about the obviously true one, but just state the conclusion yourself. Thus, when Meletus denied that Socrates believed in the existence of gods but admitted that he talked about a supernatural power, Socrates proceeded to to ask whether "supernatural beings were not either children of the gods or in some way divine?" "Yes," said Meletus. "Then," replied Socrates, "is there any one who believes in the existence of children of the gods and yet not in the existence of the gods themselves?" Another good occasion is when you expect to show that your opponent is contradicting either his own words or what every one believes. A fourth is when it is impossible for him to meet your question except by an evasive answer. If he answers "True, and yet not true," or "Partly true and partly not true," or "True in one sense but not in another," the audience thinks he is in difficulties, and applauds his discomfiture. In other cases do not attempt interrogation; for if your opponent gets in an objection, you are felt to have been worsted. You cannot ask a series of questions owing to the incapacity of the audience to follow them; and for this reason you should also make your enthymemes as compact as possible.

In replying, you must meet ambiguous questions by drawing reasonable distinctions, not by a curt answer. In meeting questions that seem to involve you in a contradiction, offer the explanation at the outset of your answer, before your opponent asks the next question or draws his conclusion. For it is not difficult to see the drift of his argument in advance. This point, however, as well as the various means of refutation, may be regarded as known to us from the Topics.

When your opponent in drawing his conclusion puts it in the form of a question, you must justify your answer. Thus when Sophocles was asked by Peisander whether he had, like the other members of the Board of Safety, voted for setting up the Four Hundred, he said "Yes." -- "Why, did you not think it wicked?" -- "Yes." -- "So you committed this wickedness?" "Yes," said Sophocles, "for there was nothing better to do." Again, the Lacedaemonian, when he was being examined on his conduct as ephor, was asked whether he thought that the other ephors had been justly put to death. "Yes," he said. "Well then," asked his opponent, "did not you propose the same measures as they?" -- "Yes." -- "Well then, would not you too be justly put to death?" -- "Not at all," said he; "they were bribed to do it, and I did it from conviction." Hence you should not ask any further questions after drawing the conclusion, [1419b] nor put the conclusion itself in the form of a further question, unless there is a large balance of truth on your side.

As to jests. These are supposed to be of some service in controversy. Gorgias said that you should kill your opponents' earnestness with jesting and their jesting with earnestness; in which he was right. Jests have been classified in the Poetics. Some are becoming to a gentleman, others are not; see that you choose such as become you. Irony better befits a gentleman than buffoonery; the ironical man jokes to amuse himself, the buffoon to amuse other people.

Previous Chapter
Lee Honeycutt (honeycuttlee@gmail.com) Last modified:3/15/04
Next Chapter